TOWARDS A PHYSICS OF CONSCIOUSNESS
Document Type:
Collection:
Document Number (FOIA) /ESDN (CREST):
CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Release Decision:
RIFPUB
Original Classification:
U
Document Page Count:
10
Document Creation Date:
November 4, 2016
Document Release Date:
August 27, 2003
Sequence Number:
4
Case Number:
Content Type:
RP
File:
Attachment | Size |
---|---|
CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9.pdf | 1020.27 KB |
Body:
Ensenanza e Investigation en Psicologia, 6, No. 1 (11), 44-52, 1980a.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J. Pachita. Las Manifestations del Ser. Editores Asociados, Mexico,
1980b.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J. EI Espacio y la Conciencia. Trillas, Mexico, 1981a.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J. The transformation of neuronal activity into conscious experience.
J. Social Biol. Structures. In press, 1981b.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J., Riefkohl, A. The spontaneous EEG coherence biofeedback
technique. Unpublished research, 1980.
Grinberg-Zylberbaum, J., Ornelas, J. Evoked potentials biofeedback techniques. Unpublished
research, 1980.
Jenny, H. Cymatics, Basel Press, Basel, 1973.
Luria, A. The Working Brain. Allen Lane, Penguin, U.S.A., 1973.
Luria, I. The Sephirot.
Pribram, H.K. Languages of the Brain. Books/Cole Pubi. Co., Monterey, California, U.S.A.,
1977.
Pur Vilayat Inhayat Khan. Personal communication, 1978.
Reite, M., Zimmerman J., Edrich, J., Zimmerman, J. The human magnetoencephalogram:
Some EEG and related correlations. Electroenceph. Clin. Neurophysiol. 40, 59-66,
1976.
Santa Teresa. LasMoradas. Austral. Espasa-Calpe, Spain, 1578, 1939, 1976.
Suzuki, Sh. Zen Mind, Beginner's Mind. Weatherhill, New York, 1977.
Torres, C., Canseco, E. La Perception del Tiempo. UNAM, Mexico, 1980.
Vivekananda, Swami. Raya Yoga. Kier, Buenos Aires, 1963, 1975.
Psychocnergctics, 1982, Vol. 4, pp. 257-274
0278-6060/82/0403-0257 $06.50/0
? Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, Inc., 1982
Printed in the United Kingdom
Towards a Physics of Consciousness
Bedford College, University of London
Parallels exist between the quantum mechanical behaviour of electrons in solids and the
characteristics of consciousness. For example, similarly to the non-localisation of electrons
inventsa crywstalithin, consciousness
emsspans all of its current contents and, just as electronic
separate at anysyst quantuminstant ar
e
e `Independent of each other, so the consciousness
of each individual is private to himself. i
Various physiological and biophysical mechanisms have, in the past, been suggested or
discovered which might conceivably permit the formation of a unified quantum system in
the sensory brain.
If conscious events are quantal events taking place in an extended system, the implication
of the time-energy uncertainty principle is that they are always in transition and that the
specious present is extended in time. This extension is necessary for the awareness of
movement or change and for the ordering of movements into a biography.
The existence of different sensory qualities makes reasonable certain hypotheses about
the topological nature of the sensory neural circuitry which is the locus of the above quantal
events.
The areas of physics known as Optics and Acoustics serve as a reminder that the
entire subject has as its raw material human observations. Pearson (1937) claimed
that physical laws merely provide brief conceptual formulae that summarise the
routine of human perception and, in agreement with him, Einstein (1922)
stated that the subject matter of all natural science consists of such sense-
perceptions as are common to different individuals and which, therefore, are to
some degree impersonal. Although it is true that more recently developed areas,
such as electricity, seem often to deal with imperceptibles, it remains the case
as Schrodinger (1950) pointed out that all information, however many ingenious
devices have been used to facilitate the labour, goes back to the sense perceptions
of some living observer. Thus, the physical world (or whatever it is whose
effects upon the observer are described by Pearson's "conceptual formulae") is
a distillation from sensation. Now, the available evidence suggests that the
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9 257
Appro.v d ForrlRelease 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
totality of a person's sensations forms his consciousness, without residue. It
can therefore be seen that the endeavour to give a physical account of conscious-
ness is an exercise in mapping the characteristics of sensation itself onto the
abstract conceptualisations which science has derived from the contents of
sensation. (This distinction between sensation and its contents might offend a
Philosopher, but, on a practical level, it corresponds to two different questions
which an observer, on seeing some object, might ask. On the one hand, he
might ask, "What kind of external (i.e. conceptual) object would produce this
sensation?" In this case he is thinking about the content of his sensation. On
the other hand, the observer might ask, "What kind of intraneural activity
Oust as conceptual as the external object) could correspond to this sensation?"
In this case, he is thinking about the sensation itself.)
Physics may conceivably be dependent upon consciousness for more than its
subject matter, however. Thus the actual numerical values of physical constants
may depend upon the fact that, had they had any other values, the universe
would have developed in ways inimical to the evolution of life and thus of
consciousness. This so-called Anthropic Principle is reviewed by Carr and Rees
(1979). If, as has been held on the basis of this principle, there is a multiplicity
of worlds with varying values for the physical constants (Everitt, 1973) and only
in some of which is consciousness possible, then the interdependence between
physical results and consciousness becomes strong indeed. Yet we may ask what
it is about the physics of this particular world that allows consciousness to
behave as it does.
2. UNITY AND SEPARATENESS
The formulae of physics are taken to describe the behaviour even of unobserved
entities, which is to say that the observer is (reasonably (Ayer, 1956)) assumed
only to form part of the physical world and to be one of many observers. If
this is the case, then we are faced with Schrodinger's "Arithmetic Paradox"
(1967). In its first form, this asks how it is that, despite the existence of many
observers, only one mind is ever experienced. If all these observers form part of
the same physical world, why is it that "plural mind" is never observed? If a
physical account is to be given of consciousness some way must be found in
which the physical world divides up into islands corresponding to the way in
which each observer's consciousness is private to himself.
The second form of Schrodinger's paradox is, in some way, the obverse of
the first and asks how the different senses, each with its own demarcated area in
the brain, can be integrated in the consciousness of a single observer. Worse
still, each component neuron of the sensory system is, in Sherrington's (1940)
words, a unit-life centred on itself and each human unit-life, or consciousness,
PHYSICS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 25 consists utterly of the cell unit-lives. What is it about this aggregate of observably
separate organisms that enables them to form a single mind?
In brief, if the world in all its detail forms a unity, why does consciousness
not encompass the whole of the world? On the other hand, if the world is
subdivisible into separate islands of identity how are brain cell lives, which under
the microscope appear as insular as separate people, to coalesce into single minds?
If physics is to help here, there must be physical principles which enable disparate
details to be in some sense identified with each. other, to form part of an
indivisible whole, in some circumstances but not in others. Such principles, if
applicable to nervous systems, would account for why each observer's experience
consists of his vision, audition, tactile sense etc. and never consists (as conceivably
it might) of a large number of for example different visual scenes.
3. QUANTUM MECHANICS AND CONSCIOUSNESS: SOME PARALLELS
Since neural activity is largely `\electrical in nature it might be expected that
the required physical principles would be found in quantum mechanics, according
to which particles of all kinds, including electrons, must be described as wavelike
entities. The behaviour of electrons, on this theory, has curious and even para-
doxical properties which seem to resemble closely the properties of consciousness.
A hint at how to construct whole systems whose parts are to form an indivisible
whole is given by the fact that electrons, in Schrodinger's words, "are not
individuals". It is not possible, that is, to identify a particular electron. This is
shown by the fact that electrons obey Pauli's "exclusion principle",(or altern-
atively behave according to Fermi-Dirac statistics) when they are in the bound
state as, for example, when confined to the "potential well" surrounding an
atomic nucleus. Schrodinger (1950) gives the following example. Suppose that
in some such confined system there are two electrons and three energy states
(corresponding to different degrees of agitation of the electronic wavefunction)
that they may occupy. Then, if the electrons were identifiable individuals,
their possible distributions over the states would be the classical (Maxwell-
Boltzmann) one shown in Figure 1. (Many atoms and molecules behave like
this.)
If, however, the particles were indistinguishable, but more than one could
occupy a state, they would have the Bose-Einstein distributions of Figure 2.
Finally, if the particles were in principle indistinguishable and lacking
individuality, they would have the Fermi-Dirac distributions of Figure 3.
The behaviour of electrons is as in Figure 3 and it is for this reason that
Schrodinger said they were not individuals. Leighton (1959) went further and
supposed that all electrons might be the same electron in a multitude of places
at the same time. However, it is to be noted that the exclusion principle whereby
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
260
J.D. VALENTINE,
Assignments
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
1
AB
A
A
B
B
State
2
B
A
AB
A
B
3
B
B
A
A
AB
PHYSICS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 26
the states of Figure 3 may not be multi-occupied and from which the nor
individuality of electrons is deduced, can only be seen to operate when electror.
are in the bound state. This is so because it is only in such states that the requirt
ment that an integral number of electron wavelengths shall fit the orbit,
restricts the successive energy levels to discrete values corresponding to 1,
3 etc. wavelengths. Beyond the maximum energy level, the electron has enoug,
energy to escape "to infinity" from the confining potential well and becaus
infinity has no endpoints there are no restrictions on wavelength and therefor.
on allowable energy levels. States in this region are therefore the "continuun
states". Since these may take arbitrarily close values, there is no sense in whici
two electrons could occupy exactly the same state. It would be wispr*, therefore
FIGURE 1 Ways of assigning two non-identical particles (A and B) to three states. There to restrict Leighton's statement to the circumstances from,-wJ ich the onl`?
are nine of these.
available evidence comes and to assert that all electrons in a system like that o
Assignments Figure 3 are the same electron. The discreteness which is thus essential to th(
non-individuality argument, gntails that in the systems with which we arc
1 2 3 4 5 6 concerned energy may only be taken up or lost in quantal packets. They wil
hereafter be referred to as quantum systems. Such systems are found not onl}
in atoms and molecules but also in metals and crystals of arbitrary size. In these
1 AA A A a lattice of atomic nuclei forms an elaborate potential well, in which the
behaviour of at least some of the electrons can be described as a complicatec
State 2 A AA A wave function spreading throughout the material with local maxima at the
atomic nuclei. This wave function, which gives the probability of finding ar.
3 A A AA electron at each point in the crystal, describes a single indivisible entity, foi
none of its electrons can be regarded as associated with any particular nucleus
and they cannot be counted.
FIGURE 2 Ways of assigning two identical particles to three states. There are six of these. There is an obvious resemblance between this state of affairs and that of
Sherrington's "single mind" arising out of the lives of its component neurons.
Assignments for in the one case we find a number of indistinguishable electrons, each originally
(before the formation of the crystal) confined to its own atom, now equally
1 2 3 likely at all times to be found in the vicinity of any nucleus in the crystal and in
the other case we find a host of separate details, each mediated by different
brain structures and cell systems, but all somehow belonging to a single observer,
1 A A as if the observer is at each time paradoxically in the presence of all the details
of his observation. Thus we seem to have the possibility that some of the
State 2 A A counter-intuitive discoveries of recent physical science can be used to account
for some of the corresponding aspects of consciousness that are puzzling on the
3 A A basis either of the classical physics of discrete entities or of the intuitive view of
the world as made up of "objects". In particular, there seems to be a possible
FIGURE 3 Ways of assigning two indistinguishable, non-individual particles to three physical resolution of Schrodinger's second Arithmetic Paradox. More attention
states. There are three of these,
will be given to the details of this in a later section. For the present, the first
Arithmetic Paradox must be reconsidered.
The world may be conceived, as far as electrons are concerned, as being made
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
262 J.D. VALENTINE'
up of a number of isolated potential wells (the regions close to atomic nuclei
etc.) each containing a number of trapped electrons which form a quantum
system. It is not an arbitrary decision where to set the limits of such a system,
for a system is isolated if the electronic states within it are independent of
changes in state of other neighbouring systems. Thus, in certain gases, any given
atom may be excited into a given state regardless of the states of surrounding
atoms. If it is a many-electron atom it is impossible, for the reasons given, to say
which electron was moved to which substate by the excitation. On the other
hand, it seems necessary to assert that the electrons that changed state were not
those belonging to other atoms in the gas. The physical justification for this lies
in the way that the energy levels of such gases follow the Maxwell-$oltzmann
distribution law which would, as in Figure 1, lead to the conclusion that the
electronic systems forming part of the separate atoms are distinguishable
individuals. The space between these potential wells is occupied by electrons "at
infinity" which remain totally unaffected by the events in any well and which
therefore do not form a coupling or link between the systems. Here again there
is a physical picture which bears a distinct resemblance to that of consciousness.
Corresponding to the consciousness of an individual spanning its contents, we
have the electronic wave spanning the crystal lattice, and corresponding to the
privacy of each mind, we have the independent Maxwellian behaviour of separate
quantum systems or crystals. The electrons forming the background for the
quantum systems are neither interacting with themselves nor with the electrons
within each system. It is only when trapped in a well that, through the exclusion
principle, they are forced to do so and when that happens, since electrons are
indistinguishable, any interaction forms one elemental event.
4. QUANTUM SYSTEMS AND NEUROPHYSIOLOGY
It is now appropriate to discuss the physiological embodiment of the foregoing.
A study of neural transmission seems at first sight to exclude the existence of
quantum systems spanning large regions of the brain. In the first place, propagation
of energy along nerves appears to be by action potentials which involve only
local currents and hence only local quantal events. The spatial separation of
neighbouring spikes by regions of nerve in the refractory phase is such that they
form independent systems. As Brink (1951) stated, the all-or-none law of neuronal
response, in which communication is by transient changes of structure or pulses
of fixed magnitude but varying rate, presents the psychologist with a fundamental
problem. Something more seems required for the explanation of mental
connectedness and continuity. .
An equally serious difficulty in the way of constructing extensive unitary
brain systems is found in the synapses through which neurons communicate,
Approved
for these characteristically contain a cleft 200nm wide across which the spike
is transmitted not electrically but by the release of chemical transmitter sub-
stances, the various molecules of which are quite separate quantum systems.
The first of these two problems would be lessened if the spike potential were
not the neural message itself but, as it were, its power supply which induces
electrical activity in some suitable intracellular structure in which electrons are
distributed somewhat as in a crystal. The notion of conduction or semiconduction
in biological macromolecules has been familiar to biologists since Szent-Gyorgyi
(1941) claimed that protein structures could have conduction bands along which
electrons could migrate; but although doubt has been cast on this (Blumenthal,
1981), there is no doubt of long range energy transfer in complexes of ,protein
molecules. Unfortunately, according to Blumenthal, the mechani?m'`for such
transfer seems often to be by resonance transfer, in which resonance is passed
nonradiatively between neighbouring molecular sites. However rapidly it might
happen, any long distance transfer-,would thus seem to consist of a sequence of
separate events, not one elemental pr quantal event as the unity of conscious
events seems to demand. A more suitable speculation, therefore, might be that
some intraneural structure has the property of superconduction which allows
long range correlation between electrons. Little (1965) has given a theoretical
account of how long protein molecules with sidechains in which electrons
resonate from one site to another can give rise to bound pairs of electrons
distributed throughout the material which, through their great number and
overlapping distributions, are required to obey the exclusion principle and to
form a quantum system. Cope (1973) has suggested that cytochrome-oxidase at
the water-lipid junctions of cell membranes may be superconducting and DNA
has a structure similar to that found necessary for superconductivity by Little.
There may conceivably be related structures that behave in the appropriate way.
Such substances could form organised lattice structures spanning whole neurons
and if the electronic system within a neuron were to be excited by field effects
generated by the spike potential this would constitute one elemental, indivisible
act.
However, the act would be confined to the neuron in question unless some
process could be found enabling electrons on opposite sides of a synaptic cleft
to become coupled. Some, though a minority, of vertebrate synapses possess
greatly narrowed clefts, accompanied by intercellular channels known as gap
junctions (Sotelo, Llinas and Baker, 1974), and which are associated with
electrical transmission. Unwin and Zampighi (1980) have analysed how these
junctions open to join the intracellular spaces. The usual account (Kuffler and
Nichols, 1976) of the functioning of these narrow clefts is that by preventing
its shunting into the extracellular fluid, they allow the local current circuit to
pass unhindered from cell to cell. That may be true at the level of the spike
potential but gives the gaps no electrical function. At the level of the supposed
Approved For Release 2003/09/10: CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
J.O. VAIAA HNL
superconducting core it may be that the opening of the gaps, having been
powered by the spike potential, the lattice structures of the two cells are brought
into contact so that the events within them are happening to a single quantum
system. If the gaps only open when both cells are firing, the second cell will
only be coupled with the first when both are active. By such means, large
oscillatory systems whose contributory neurons will depend upon sensory input
could be formed. (Of course other mechanisms for coupling the electronic
systems of co-active neurons might be DostnlafPd C-
(IOQm -L- -
b
State
c
(energy level)
d
PHYSICS OF CONSCIOUSNESS
ueias may span even high-resistance synapses. But it is
to be observed that the cleft width in electrically transmitting synapses is about
2nm (Kuffler and Nichols, op. cit. p. 158), somewhere around the electronic
tunnelling distance (deVault and Chance, 1966) and similar in extent to the
insulating junctions (about Inm) between superconducting bars across which
direct current can be observed to flow in the Josephson effect and which is
attributed to phase coupling of the electron pairs in the two bars through
quantum tunnelling.) The changing contents of consciousness, n this
Supposition, reflect the fact that continually different cell systems aroe being
switched into and out of the overall quantum system. The vast number of such
systems, corresponding to features not currently present, which are uncoupled
from the main quantum system remain quantum systems in themselves but
play no part in consciousness. They, as much as "matter", correspond to J.S.
Mill's "permanent possibility of sensation".
5. MENTAL EVENTS, THE PRESENT AND TIME
If it is true, as many following Titchener (1909) have claimed, that conscious-
ness is entirely made up of sensations and that these correspond to the activation
of appropriate feature detecting cell systems and their coupling to the main
brain quantum system (i.e. to activity in areas serving other sense modalities) via
brainstem structures, we conclude that a mental event corresponds to a quantal
uptake or loss of energy by the whole presently coupled sensory system. Th
state of affairs has profound implications for what appears in consciousness. is
Each new sensory change, however small, changes the mental event representing
the contents of consciousness; tends, that is, to prepare the sensory brain in a
state corresponding to the total sensory array at that time. However, as Haldane
(1963) pointed out in an article that anticipated the present view of the quantal
nature of mental events, the energies of neighbouring states in a system as
extensive as the sensory brain are very close together. This means that the
transition from one mental state to another involves very precisely defined,
because very small, amounts of energy. Now, the time-energy uncertainty
principle dictates that the more precisely the e
nergy of a quantal transition is
FIGURE 4 Diagram to illustrate how the successive presentation of five stimulus configur-
atstations (C, to C,) which, other things being equal, would prepare the brain in a corresponding
e (d, e, b, a and c respectively), affects the probability that the system is in each state.
This probability is represented by the width of the bulge in the line representing each
state.
determined the less precisely it may be timed. For stimulated transitions, saye,
from state A to state B which involve precise energies, the probability that th
system is in state B rather than state A changes continuously over time, even
though measurement on the system at any time would show itwto be either in
state A or in state B. Thus, although a measurement of a state will always give
an unambiguous result, the state itself must be viewed as a changing mixture of
states. Haldane calculated that such transitions in a system as extensive as the
brain might be expected to take about a second. However, sensory inputs arrive
at a much higher rate than one a second and so at any time the total system is in
a changing mixture of states in the above sense. Haldane used this fact to
account for how events in consciousness seem to overlap and include each other
so that the psychological, specious, present is not of infinitesimal duration but
seems to include events spread over about a second. Schematically the situation
is as in Figure 4 which shows the effect of five successive sensory configurations
(Cl to C5) upon the state of the sensory quantum system.
Given a relation between rate of stimulus presentation and transition time
like that in the diagram, we should conclude that the conscious system will
never certainly be in a state. Rather it will be in several states which are spread
in time: a measurement on the system at time tt would show it either to be in
state d or e, while at time t2 such a measurement would
h
s
ow it either to be in
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP e00 2P,60b46bOpW6 ical moment which we are equating with the
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
.iD. VALIiNTINL?'
state of the system therefore has a length governed by the time it takes for any
constituent state to enter and be purged from the mixture of states. As Haldane
(1963) suggested, in their possession
opportunity to examine of consciousness human beings have the
the quantum theoretic assertion that quantal events
have no detail (in that there are no states between the possible energy states, so
that transitions are all or none). It might be added to this that, similarly, human
observers might examine the physical assertion that although observables are
discrete, the state variables change continuously. Bohm (1980) referred to the
Zeno-like paradox that a moving object seems to be apprehended as a series of
"stills" each separate and selfcontained, yet flow of movement. He proceeded to say that this 2000 year old problem individed
still
lacked a satisfactory answer, but it is proposed here than quantum theory
gives a perfectly adequate answer, viz. the sensory system is in a continuously
changing mixture of discrete (or orthogonal) states. The changing
of being observed to be in a state is to be identified with the sense of flowing
movement and the discrete (but coexistent) states with the "stills".
It is arguable that the construction of an abstract dimension of time depends
crucially upon the fact that the irreducible instant in sensation is itself changing.
If sensory events occurred at a much slower rate than transitions, as schematised
in Figure 5, there would exist a series of discrete mental events well separated in
time with nothing to indicate their inherent continuity and ordering.
The non-mental nature of the pure states between transitions is weakly
supported by the fact that conscious events are always changing, so that transition
Time
FIGURE 5 Diagram of changing states in a sensory system in which inputs occur at a
slower rate than transitions. The corresponding mental events (the transitions E, to E4) are
seen to be non-overlapping and so contain no information as to their ordering.
seems the crucial mechanism, and is further suggested by the fact of general
anaesthesia. Presumably the effect of an anaesthetic is, through nullifying
membrane activity, to leave the system in some stable state (perhaps the ground
state), but that unchanging state corresponds to unconsciousness. The mental
existence of the observer of Figure 5, therefore, would consist of a series of
momentary disconnected comings to life.
Mental events like any other physical events, then, only occur when matter
waves change state and the continuity of a person's biography consists in the
string of overlapping transitions between states of the matter waves trapped
within the potential well formed by the atomic nuclei of his sensory nervous
system. Only in such transitions does the indivisible electron wave havq.to keep
out of its own way, so to speak, in order to obey the Pauli Principle,:
6. MEASUREMENT, THE PREPARATION OF STATES, AND REPORTING
ON CONSCIOUSNESS
We have distinguished between the state of a system which is capable of smooth
variation and observables (e.g. physical quantities like energy) which are discrete
and experimentally always yield exactly one value and so, in any single experi-
ment, misrepresent the underlying process. It might be asked, if this is so, how
it is possible to report upon consciousness and its contents, for surely, in order
to report upon events in a system, measurements must be made upon it so that
one would expect the report not only to misrepresent the state of affairs in the
above way but also to prepare the system in a new state which wound be a
function of the measurement and so not an uncontaminated state of the system
itself.
To answer this question, it should be pointed out that the statement that a
person observes his awareness, or part of it, is not as simple as it may appear.
The mental activity of a person is more extensive than his consciousness and a
great proportion of it never enters his consciousness. Freud (1954) distinguished
between conscious and unconscious subsets of mental activity and James (1890)
spoke of the "flights and perchings" of thought. The perchings refer to those
moments during thinking when images, or phrases representing suggested
solutions to the problem, presented themselves to the thinker's consciousness,
whereas the flights were those inferred processes intervening between the
perchings and which produced them by some means entirely outside the thinker's
awareness. According to the above hypothesis, there is no necessity for. these
processes to be unconscious in themselves. All that is required is that the
association cortex (A) shall be permanently decoupled electronically from the
sensory system (S), even though they may interact intimately by some non-
electronic pro s . t- of these two systems are entirely different:
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R6OO400b1V664t? o
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
268 J.D. VALENTINE PHYSICS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 269
S serves as the definer of moments, the coordinator of disparate inputs into
elaborate patterns of input, while A serves to anticipate subsequent patterns on
the basis of the present one. This it seems to do by forming what Bindra (1976)
calls contingency organizations between sets of features (gnostic assemblies)
that experience shows to stand in a predictive relation with other such sets. The
production of motor responses is supposed to be brought about when such a
contingency organization predicts a situation capable of eliciting the movements
in question (or preactivates sensory features connected maturationally to the
appropriate motor apparatus). Now A only requires as input the outputs
(corresponding to various sensory features) of S to use them predictively and,
ultimately, to base a vocalised description upon. It follows that any "description"
of consciousness or its contents must amount to a listing of features present -
the features themselves cannot be described. However, if an observer sets
himself, for example, the task of describing the "straightness" of a line, this
instruction, through a multitude of contingency organizations of which he is
not aware, will preactivate the neurons of the straightness (or edge-detecting)
systems, which will have the effect of enhancing activity in those regions at the
expense of others. The conscious experience will then be more purely one of
"straightness". Thus the reporting on a certain demanded aspect of experience
enhances that very aspect. However, the report cannot do anything but state
whether the aspect, or associated aspects, is present. Therefore, while the A
system has been set an impossible task, it yet indicates to the S system the
solution it cannot verbalise. According to this view, when consciousness is
apparently being reported upon, in these examples, there is a one-to-many
mapping of the association cortex's report onto the activity within the feature
analysers that allow the report to be made. Schematically the situation is as in
Figure 6.
FIGURE 6 Diagram showing the nature of association between sensory features. A, and
S. are feature analysing circuits whose outputs may be associated by the circuitry in A.
If it be supposed that all motor responding is produced by the A system
(through its selective priming of sensory apparatus adequate for the response) it
is clear that no description can be given of internal aspects of feature experience,
since no information about it is communicated to the A system.
7. DIFFERING SENSORY QUALITIES AND NEURAL ORGANIZATION
The last question concerning conscious awareness that will be considered here,
is that which Schrodinger called the mystery of the sensory qualities. He stated
the difficulty in terms of there being nowhere in the neural account of brain
activity any colour or emotion. But the reason for this is plain: the neural
account of brain activity is not that activity but rather a conceptual description
based on a series of observations of the activity's external effects. He?e again the
state of a system should be distinguished from its corresponding observables.
On this basis, it may be asserted that redness, for example, is in the brain if by
that we mean that redness constitutes the activity in some part of what out-
wardly looks like a brain. Sensations are the process in itself and not observations
carried out on that process.
The problem of differing sensory qualities is why activity in some parts of
brain is accompanied by sensations of colour while in others it is accompanied
by sounds and so on. It is possible that a consideration of the nature of these
various modalities could lead to some notion of what the circuitry involved in
it would look like if observed. This task is somewhat similar to that of the
astronomer who tries to deduce the four dimensional shape of the universe from
within his three dimensions. The observer's task is to discover his shape without
ever going outside his boundaries. The main difference between the two is that
the observer extends throughout the pattern of activity whose shape he is to
deduce.
Now each sense modality in reality consists of a number of submodalities
somewhat arbitrarily conjoined. For example, the visual modality, representing
all those sensations achievable by opening the eyes, contains colour, shape,
movement and depth aspects among others. It is not clear that straightness and
redness as submodalities are more akin (more essentially "visual") than, say
redness and the sound of a pure middle C and so the investigator should be
prepared to analyse each modality into its phenomenally irreducible aspects.
If he succeeds, he will probably have got down to the level of feature analysers
like those of Figure 6, and the reason for their irreducibility will be that such
analysers have only a single output. At any rate, he will not be able to dissect
his experience further.
We may predict, therefore, that little progress will be made in discovering
why the activity in the "yellow" circuit gives a feeling of yellowness, but this
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
J.D. VALENTINE
will not prevent some progress from being made. For example, "depth" or
spatial location may be felt in at least two modalities, the visual and the auditory.
For each of these sensory systems compares inputs from two sides to achieve
its end. It will not, therefore, be surprising if some aspects of their circuitry are
rather similar. If they are, it would seem appropriate to say that depth is a
separate modality but with independent realisations in the visual and auditory
spheres.
This hint that the quality of a sensation depends on the organisation of the
corresponding feature detectors prompts the question as to what principles of
organization are the crucial ones. If modalities are studied as wholes an answer
to this question is suggested. In vision, for example, different aspects of a scene
are contributed by different levels of the nervous system. Thus, the spatial
location of an object requires the operation of the superior colliculus, while
its detailed features are analysed by the cortex (Schneider, 1969). This situation
in which different types of feature are analysed in different locations separated
by rather lengthy fibre tracts is perhaps to be expected, since more recently
evolved brain structures should provide more detailed information about the
environment than older ones. Despite this spatial separation of the analysers
involved, the location, brightness, colour and shape of an object are felt to be
intimately connected and intertwined - the colour of an object is felt to be
coextensive with the object and never (as in colour printing) do the colour and
the shape fail to coincide. This observation makes it clear that it is not the
geometry of the neural organization that is crucial, for that would seem to
overemphasize the spatial differentiation of the various analysing systems.
Rather the sensation corresponds to the topological description of the system,
since that is concerned with relations of containment, adjacency and so on
which are independent of geometrical transformations; so that, for example,
one object may contain another even though the bulk of the two objects may
be spatially widely separated. By such means we may hope to explain how an
object always "contains" its colours even though shape and colour are analysed
by different structures.
Since most of perception is of qualities at locations, it is pertinent to ask why
some patterns of neural activity are spatially differentiated and some non-
spatially differentiated in sensation. In Figure 7, two schematic patterns of
neural activity are represented.
From the previous discussion, it appears that the activity within neural fibre
tracts does not contribute to awareness but merely connects different sets of
feature analysers reflecting the fact that topologically a line is a point. We will
provisionally assume therefore that neural activity contributes to conscious
awareness when it is organized. The minimum unit of organization is a loop and
it is in terms of these that Figure 7 wil be discussed.
In (a) each loop of three adjacent points is either in contact with another
FIGURE 7 Two imaginary patterns of neural activity to illustrate the argument in the
text. When an intersection does not have a dot, the lines are not joined but merely e,oss.
such loop or with many that are. There is a high degree of adjacency between
loops. In (b), on the other hand, each loop of three points is adjacent only to a
select few other loops. Now, it is`v-haracteristic of "space" that each point is
adjacent to very few other points i'n exactly the same way as the loops of (b)
are adjacent. Although the neural network of (a) or (b) may, seen from the
outside, be warped, stretched or crumpled out of recognition, the experiencer of
the activity within it will only be aware of the adjacencies, so that to him the
elements of (b) will be held apart and seem spatial while those of (a) will seem
to possess a point quality of some kind, since only for a point are all the "parts"
adjacent to each other. TheFexact nature of the quality will depend upon the
number of points and their pattern of interaction - the graph theoretic concept
of "genus" (the number of "handles" that must be "sewn" onto a "sphere"
in order to embed a figure) is probably relevant here: the topological inequivalence
of graphs of different genus may well be one basis for the seemingly irreconcilable
differences between sensory qualities. It must remain an empirical matter to
establish which graphs correspond to which sensations, in exactly the same way
as it was an empirical matter to discover which molecular structure corresponds
to what we know as water.
Now, if a network of type (a) be attached to each node of network (b) by
a tenuous link, say a single fibre, from the point of view of the experiencer of
the network, it can be seen that non-spatial, punctate, qualities will be felt at
each node and since the various cycles of (b) are held apart in a spatial manner,
for the experiencer the quality in question will be felt, as in seeing a coloured
object, to extend over an area of space. In some cases the mutual adjacency of
the parts of a feature analyser may be less extreme than in the above example.
This will add a certain spatial aspect to the sensory quality. Rich (1916) identified
a dimension of voluminousness of sounds and parametric studies by Thomas
(1949) showed that pure tones of e.g. 200Hz, 22db and 4000Hz, 100db were
consistently judged as of equal volume.
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Sensory qualities are "mysterious" because there is no output to the A
system from their internal parts. If evolution had found it expedient to provide
such outputs from, say, the various subprocesses involved in the redness circuit,
then human observers would be able to describe it in greater detail. However,
not only would this "description" be of the strictly limited kind referred to
above but also the subprocesses themselves would then become "mysterious".
Descriptions of sensation therefore can shed light on the topological arrangement
of feature detectors, but only in a general way enable the internal structure of
feature detectors to be established.
Anatomically the brain has just the topological organization described above.
All sensory inputs pass through the reticular formation, which is very highly
internally connected, on to higher and higher levels of midbrain and cortex: in
the visual regions each of these higher structures arises out of its own peculiar
lower structure and has very little lateral connexion with similar neighbouring
structures. In this way, the topological containments (of quality-mechanisms
in location-mechanisms) that seem necessary for the construction of visual space
are achieved. Different modalities have their separate bundles of columnar
machinery with varying internal arrangements. Thus the geography of the brain
reflects the characteristics of conscious experience with its different modalities
(the different sensory areas) unified into a single "self" (joined into a functional
unity via the reticular formation and other midbrain structures). Commenting
on the dotted grid-pattern of activity in cortical edge-detectors when one eye
of a monkey is exposed to a set of vertical stripes, Hubel and Wiesel (1979)
write, "Imagine the surprise and bewilderment of a little green man looking
at such a version of the outside world!" However, the cortical activity is not a
version of the outside world but merely part of one: for the total version, all
the appropriate activity from lower centres would have to be included. The
actual "little green man" is embedded in the activity at all levels simultaneously
and because he is only aware of topological relationships in that activity he sees
a set of vertical stripes. Whereabouts in the cortex the verticality of each part of
each stripe is registered is irrelevant to the resulting perception and, were he
well-informed, the geometric external appearance of his brain activity need not
surprise him at all.
events and thus the consciousness of the individual. Other regions of brain do
not contribute to consciousness for one, or more, of three reasons: their
electronic disconnexion, their inactivity and their sequential, as opposed to
spatial, mode of action. Concerning disconnextion, it seems plausible that
electronic coupling only exists between "hardwired" circuits of cells such as
those of feature detectors and not between cells whose ability to excite each
other is conditional upon experience and which must be reversible. If so, the
"flights" of thought take place in the latter kind of cell. It is possible that there
is some kind of consciousness in other tightly knit regions, such as the cerebellum
which, as an autonomous controller of movements, is independent of the main
sensory system. The consciousness that is referred to as belonging to the
individual corresponds to the quantal events in that region of the braii Mihose
activity is a necessary precursor of so called voluntary movements and of speech.
Any other consciousness within the individual's brain is as foreign to that
individual as another person's consciousness and for the same reasons. With
regard to inactivity, each potential, but presently unrealised sensation,
corresponds to cell systems which, through lack of input, are inactive so that
they are both decoupled from the main system and are making no transitions.
(They are effectively anaesthetised.) Even if electronic events were taking place
in them as a result of, say, spontaneous activity, such events would be both
rudimentary and switched out of the main system, so that at any particular time
no contribution is made to awareness by large tracts of sensory brain. Finally,
concerning a sequential mode of working such as we might expect to find in the
association cortex, whose function is to predict one sensory array from a
previous one, we may note that to get from one array to another neural events
must pass through some process which is not an array and since all sensation
forms an array, this process will not contribute to consciousness.
There is no mystery of how the arrangement of different sensory mechanisms
produces the corresponding sensation, for these mechanisms must be seen merely
as conceptual abstractions and not things-in-themselves. It is the privilege of
human observers to be things-in-themselves that have (via the sensorimotor
system) some limited capacity to discuss their own nature with each other.
Other things-in-themselves (atoms, molecules and larger structures) must remain
forever mute; but it is to be presumed that, in principle, they differ from us only
in the degree of complexity of their existence.
The sensory brain can thus be viewed as a collection of dense networks of
varying internal connectivity joined together by a kind of tree structure of
neural tracts. These networks are individually capable of being activated and
switched into (and out of) the total network. It is quantal electronic transitions
within the currently connected networks that form the overlapping conscious
Ayer, A.J. The Problem of Knowledge, Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1956.
Bindra, D. A Theory of Intelligent Behaviour, Wiley Interscience, New York, 1976.
Blumenthal, L.A. Problems of Biological Physics, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1981.
Bohm, D. Wholeness and the Implicate Order, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1980.
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Approved For Release 2003/09/10 : CIA-RDP96-00792R000400010004-9
Brink, F. Excitation and conduction in the neurone. Handbook of Experimental Psychology
(ed. Stevens, S.S.), Wiley, New York, 1951.
Carr, B.J., Rees, M.J. The anthropic principle and the structure of the physical world.
Nature, 278, 605-612, 1979.
Cope, F.W. Electron-phonon (trapped photon) coupling and infrared coaxial transmission
line theory of energy transport in mitochondria and nerve. Bull. Math. Biol., 35,
627-644,1973.
Einstein, A. The Meaning of Relativity, Methuen, London, 1922.
Everitt, H.H. The theory of the universal wave function. The Many-Worlds Interpretation
of Quantum Mechanics (eds. De Witt, B., Graham, N.), Princeton Univ. Press, 1973.
Freud, S. The Origins of Psychoanalysis; Letters to Wilhem Fliess, Drafts and Notes, Basic
Books, New York, 1954.
Haldane, J.B.S. Life and mind as physical realities. Penguin ScienceSurveyB, 224-238,1963.
Hubel, D.H., Wiesel, T.N. Brain mechanisms of vision. The Brain, W.H. Freeman, New York,
1979.
James, W. The Principles of Psychology, Holt, New York, 1890.
Kuffler, S.W., Nicholls, J.G. From Neuron to Brain, Sinauer, Sunderland, Mass., 1976.
Leighton, R.B. Principles of Modern Physics, McGraw Hill, New York, 1959.
Little, W.A. Superconductivity at room temperature. Scl. Am., 212, No. 2, 21-27, 1965.
Pearson, K. The Grammar of Science, Dent, London, 1937.
Rich, G.J. A preliminary study of tonal volume. J. Exp. Psychol., 1, 13-22, 1916.
Ruffner, J.A., Sperelakis, N., Mann, J.E. Application of the Hodgkin-Huxley equations to
an electrical model for interaction between excitable cells. J. Theor. Biol., 87, 129-
152, 1980.
Schneider, G.E. Two visual systems. Science, 163, 895-902, 1969.
Schrodinger, E. What is an elementary particle? Ann. Rep. Smithsonian Inst., 183-196,
1950.
Schrodinger, E. What is Life, Mind and Matter? Camb. Univ. Press, 1967.
Sherrington, C.S. Man on his Nature, Camb. Univ. Press, 1940.
Sotelo, C., Llinas, R., Baker, R. Structural study of inferior olivary nucleus of the cat:
morphological correlates of electronic coupling. J. Neurophysiol., 37, 541-559,1974.
Szent-Gyorgyi, A. The study of energy levels in biochemistry. Nature, 148, 157-159, 1941.
Titchener, E.B. Lectures on the Experimental Psychology of the Thought Processes,
Macmillan, New York, 1909.
Thomas, G.T. Equal-volume judgements of tones. Amer. J. Psychol., 62, 182-201, 1949.
Unwin, P.N.T., Zampighi, G. Structure of the junction between communicating cells.
Nature, 283, 545-549, 1980.
Psychoenergetics, 1982, Vol. 4, pp. 275-278
0278-6060/82/0403-0275 $06.50/0
? Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, Inc., 1982
Printed in the United Kingdom
Evolution and Atoms
It is argued that the modern evolutionary conception of nature forces us temonclude that
even simple atoms and molecules are psychophysical systems. It is suggested that modern
physics has already, tacitly, begun to describe the psychic aspect of microphysical objects.
Quantum nonlocality is interpreted as a form of acausal perception and seen as the founda-
tion of both the paranormal and the more complex overlying phenomena of everyday
psychology. 1,
We know ourselves both as centres of subjective experience and as objective
bodies. Not only are we made of flesh and blood but also of sensations, thoughts
and feelings. If we accept the modern theory of evolution, this fact - the co-
existence of these two complementary aspects of a human being - has impor-
tant implications for our conception of the simplest material objects, i.e. atoms
and their constituents. .
Human beings have evolved from.the higher mammals. These also experience
sensations and feelings. We know this from the fact that their sense organs
strongly resemble our own, and that they exhibit the gestures and reactions
which characteristically accompany our own various emotions. Who, in the
presence of a shrieking, injured animal, or seeing an animal cower away from
him, can seriously doubt that it is experiencing feelings of pain or fear similar to
our own? The more developed higher mammals, such as apes or dolphins, also
exhibit some degree of reflective intelligence.
The further back down the evolutionary tree we go, the harder it becomes to
imagine the kind of subjective experience the creatures possess. Their sensory
apparatus and forms of behaviour are quite unlike ours. Indeed, at a low level,
such as that of the insects, for example, we may be inclined to believe that they
have no inward experience at all, but are mere mechanical automata. In that
case, where should we draw the line? Which were the first organisms to emerge
capable not only of acting and reacting but also of experiencing the world
around them?
This question assumes that it is possible for a transition from inert material
bb~~
For Release 2003/09/10 : ClA-RDP96-QO t S~la 6010004p9riencetohaveoccurredintheprocessofevolution.
Approved
Z 275