WHY CAN'T WE ACT AGAINST TERRORISM?

Document Type: 
Collection: 
Document Number (FOIA) /ESDN (CREST): 
CIA-RDP90-00552R000302440001-9
Release Decision: 
RIPPUB
Original Classification: 
K
Document Page Count: 
1
Document Creation Date: 
December 22, 2016
Document Release Date: 
July 15, 2010
Sequence Number: 
1
Case Number: 
Publication Date: 
July 1, 1985
Content Type: 
OPEN SOURCE
File: 
AttachmentSize
PDF icon CIA-RDP90-00552R000302440001-9.pdf92.79 KB
Body: 
Sanitized Copy Approved for Release 2010/07/15: CIA-RDP90-00552R000302440001-9 STAT E ON ON PAGE - WASHINGTON POST 1 July 1985 Alexander JI. Haig Jr. Why 't We Act Against Terrorism? Can Three fallacies cloud our thinking. It is urgent to develop a more effective American policy against terrorism. Americans in particular are increasingly the victims of this ugly phenomenon. From the hostages in Iran five years ago to the most recent ordeal in Bei- rut. a lengthening shadow has been cast over the U.S. presence abroad. Why are we so often the targets? Surely not because we are weak. Since World War U, our nuclear and conventional forces have been largely successful in deterring outright aggres- sion. Paradoxically, precisely because we are strong, the terrorists and their allies seek to chip away at our morale, our domestic order and our international prestige-the shadow of our power, as Dean Acheson put it. Precisely because we are democratic, be- cause we believe in individual rights, the terror- ist method is to pit our reverence for innocent life against our natural instinct to defend our- selves. And it is precisely because we believe in an international order, in which necessary change can take place peacefully, that terrorists find their natural allies among those who wish to remake the world forcibly in their own totali- tarian image. Why have we been unable to act more effec- tively against terrorism? Three important falla- cies cloud our thinking. First is the fallacy that terrorism lives on its own organic resources, independent of state aid. We must be able to discriminate, of course; among the acts of deranged individuals, obscure groups possessed by violent political doctrines and the full-fledged agents of government. Yet difficult as this may be, one thing is easy to discern: terrorism's success breeds growing support. Libya, Iran and Syria employ terror because they believe it works. The Soviet Union, sometimes through East Germany and Bulgaria, bears a heavy responsibility. All of these states want political change by force; they want to turn the balance of power against the democracies. State-sponsored terrorism is but one element along a spectrum of violence intended to trans- form the international brder. If we forget this, then we are bound to miss the larger issue- the difference between democratic and totali- tarian regimes with respect to international change. Second comes the moral fallacy that some- how counterterrorist action, which may risk in- nocent fives, "dirties" our hands. This fallacy condemns us to paralysis and puts the terrorist and his victims-and the United States is a vic- tim-on the same moral plane. The use of force may miscarry. Military operations do go awry. But the alternative to risking a few precious lives today may be to risk many more no less precious lives tomorrow, as terrorists and the governments that support them become convinced that we lack the moral strength to defend our values. This fallacy has just about crippled our de- bate over terrorism. We see senior U.S. off i- cials threatening preemption when we have yet to succeed at retaliation, and setting forth conditions for the use of our military forces so ideal that they have rarely been met even in wartime, All this talk only increases the pres- sure for ill-considered action in the hope of re- covering a self-damaged sense of virility. The third fallacy is the fear that concerted action against terrorism or its state sponsors somehow sacrifices more important issues. A case in point: the fear that a full expose of the plot to kill the pope may complicate efforts to reduce tensions with the U.S.S.R. Another case in point: our curious silence over the Syrian role in terrorism after our departure from Lebanon. Obviously, we must be prudent in dealing with such states sponsoring terrorism, but prudence can never be an excuse to avoid the truth. We must deter terrorism by lowering the re- wards and raisins the penalties for those who en- courage it. This includes both improved intelli- . im roved human sources of intelligence The most important initiative, however, is to rally concerted international action: political, eco- nomic, diplomatic and military. It works. Libya's Muammar Qaddafi was forced onto the defen- sive in 1981-82 by such measures until nearly everyone resumed business as usual. But we are under no obligation to adhere to a multilat- eral suicide pact if international action is not forthcoming. Then we must act alone. In the final analysis, our character as a free people is being tested. Are we too irresolute, too concerned with the ebb and flow of public opinion, too "short of breath" as the Syrians boasted following the Marine withdrawal? I think not. The writer was secretary of state from 1981 to June 1982. Sanitized Copy Approved for Release 2010/07/15: CIA-RDP90-00552R000302440001-9